Welcome to the community hub built on top of the Coherency (homotopy theory) Wikipedia article.
Here, you can discuss, collect, and organize anything related to Coherency (homotopy theory). The
purpose of...
Often, more than one way of defining a mapping between mathematical objects might be considered "natural". Then the question might arise, which way to choose? Coherency implies that it doesn't matter which way is chosen, because all the alternative definitions are equivalent. The equivalence is often manifest in a commutative diagram.
The adjectives such as "pseudo-" and "lax-" are used to refer to the fact equalities are weakened in coherent ways; e.g., pseudo-functor, pseudoalgebra.
In some situations, isomorphisms need to be chosen in a coherent way. Often, this can be achieved by choosing canonical isomorphisms. But in some cases, such as prestacks, there can be several canonical isomorphisms and there might not be an obvious choice among them.
In practice, coherent isomorphisms arise by weakening equalities; e.g., strict associativity may be replaced by associativity via coherent isomorphisms. For example, via this process, one gets the notion of a weak 2-category from that of a strict 2-category.
Replacing coherent isomorphisms by equalities is usually called strictification or rectification.
A coherence condition is a collection of conditions requiring that various compositions of elementary morphisms are equal. Typically the elementary morphisms are part of the data of the category. A coherence theorem states that, in order to be assured that all these equalities hold, it suffices to check a small number of identities.
Part of the data of a monoidal category is a chosen morphism
, called the associator:
for each triple of objects in the category. Using compositions of these , one can construct a morphism
Actually, there are many ways to construct such a morphism as a composition of various . One coherence condition that is typically imposed is that these compositions are all equal.[1]
Typically one proves a coherence condition using a coherence theorem, which states that one only needs to check a few equalities of compositions in order to show that the rest also hold. In the above example, one only needs to check that, for all quadruples of objects , the following diagram commutes.
Any pair of morphisms from to constructed as compositions of various are equal.
Let f : A → B be a morphism of a category containing two objects A and B. Associated with these objects are the identity morphisms 1A : A → A and 1B : B → B. By composing these with f, we construct two morphisms:
f o 1A : A → B, and
1B o f : A → B.
Both are morphisms between the same objects as f. We have, accordingly, the following coherence statement:
Let f : A → B, g : B → C and h : C → D be morphisms of a category containing objects A, B, C and D. By repeated composition, we can construct a morphism from A to D in two ways:
(h o g) o f : A → D, and
h o (g o f) : A → D.
We have now the following coherence statement:
(h o g) o f = h o (g o f).
In these two particular examples, the coherence statements are theorems for the case of an abstract category, since they follow directly from the axioms; in fact, they are axioms. For the case of a concrete mathematical structure, they can be viewed as conditions, namely as requirements for the mathematical structure under consideration to be a concrete category, requirements that such a structure may meet or fail to meet.
Mac Lane's coherence theorem states, roughly, that if diagrams of certain types commute, then diagrams of all types commute.[2] A simple proof of that theorem can be obtained using the permutoassociahedron, a polytope whose combinatorial structure appears implicitly in Mac Lane's proof.[3]
There are several generalizations of Mac Lane's coherence theorem.[4] Each of them has the rough form that "every weak structure of some sort is equivalent to a stricter one".[5]
Ch. 5 of Kamps, Klaus Heiner; Porter, Timothy (April 1997). Abstract Homotopy and Simple Homotopy Theory. World Scientific. doi:10.1142/2215. ISBN9810216025.
Kapranov, Mikhail M. (1993). "The permutoassociahedron, Mac Lane's coherence theorem and asymptotic zones for the KZ equation". Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra. 85 (2): 119–142. doi:10.1016/0022-4049(93)90049-Y.
Calaque, Damien; Etingof, Pavel (2008). "Lectures on tensor categories". Quantum Groups. IRMA Lectures in Mathematics and Theoretical Physics. Vol. 12. pp. 1–38. arXiv:math/0401246. doi:10.4171/047-1/1. ISBN978-3-03719-047-0.
Kelly, G.M (1964). "On MacLane's conditions for coherence of natural associativities, commutativities, etc". Journal of Algebra. 1 (4): 397–402. doi:10.1016/0021-8693(64)90018-3.
Kelly, G. M.; Laplaza, M.; Lewis, G.; Mac Lane, Saunders (1972). Coherence in Categories. Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Vol. 281. doi:10.1007/BFb0059553. ISBN978-3-540-05963-9.
Im, Geun Bin; Kelly, G.M. (1986). "A universal property of the convolution monoidal structure". Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra. 43: 75–88. doi:10.1016/0022-4049(86)90005-8.
Laplaza, Miguel L. (1972). "Coherence for distributivity". Coherence in Categories. Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Vol. 281. pp. 29–65. doi:10.1007/BFb0059555. ISBN978-3-540-05963-9.
MacLane, Saunders; Paré, Robert (1985). "Coherence for bicategories and indexed categories". Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra. 37: 59–80. doi:10.1016/0022-4049(85)90087-8.
Power, A.J. (1989). "A general coherence result". Journal of Pure and Applied Algebra. 57 (2): 165–173. doi:10.1016/0022-4049(89)90113-8.