Hubbry Logo
search button
Sign in
Perfect set property
Perfect set property
Comunity Hub
History
arrow-down
starMore
arrow-down
bob

Bob

Have a question related to this hub?

bob

Alice

Got something to say related to this hub?
Share it here.

#general is a chat channel to discuss anything related to the hub.
Hubbry Logo
search button
Sign in
Perfect set property
Community hub for the Wikipedia article
logoWikipedian hub
Welcome to the community hub built on top of the Perfect set property Wikipedia article. Here, you can discuss, collect, and organize anything related to Perfect set property. The purpose of the hub is to...
Add your contribution
Perfect set property

In the mathematical field of descriptive set theory, a subset of a Polish space has the perfect set property if it is either countable or has a nonempty perfect subset (Kechris 1995, p. 150). Note that having the perfect set property is not the same as being a perfect set.

As nonempty perfect sets in a Polish space always have the cardinality of the continuum, and the reals form a Polish space, a set of reals with the perfect set property cannot be a counterexample to the continuum hypothesis, stated in the form that every uncountable set of reals has the cardinality of the continuum.

The Cantor–Bendixson theorem states that closed sets of a Polish space X have the perfect set property in a particularly strong form: any closed subset of X can be written uniquely as the disjoint union of a perfect set and a countable set. In particular, every uncountable Polish space has the perfect set property, and can be written as the disjoint union of a perfect set and a countable open set.

As a consequence, if a subset of a Polish space is such that its derived sets eventually reach the empty set, that is, for some ordinal , then is countable.

The axiom of choice implies the existence of sets of reals that do not have the perfect set property, such as Bernstein sets. However, in Solovay's model, which satisfies all axioms of ZF but not the axiom of choice, every set of reals has the perfect set property, so the use of the axiom of choice is necessary. Every analytic set has the perfect set property. It follows from the existence of sufficiently large cardinals that every projective set has the perfect set property.

Generalizations

[edit]

Let be the least uncountable ordinal. In an analog of Baire space derived from the -fold cartesian product of with itself, any closed set is the disjoint union of an -perfect set and a set of cardinality , where -closedness of a set is defined via a topological game in which members of are played.[1]

References

[edit]
  • Kechris, Alexander S. (1995), Classical Descriptive Set Theory, Berlin, New York: Springer-Verlag, ISBN 978-1-4612-8692-9

Citations

[edit]
  1. ^ J. Väänänen, "A Cantor-Bendixson theorem for the space ". Fundamenta Mathematicae vol. 137, iss. 3, pp.187--199 (1991).